Stoicism, stoicism, and mental health

Clint Eastwood Good Bad and UglyYou can tell Stoicism is getting popular when anyone who disagrees with me on Twitter resorts to the “argument” (I’m using the word very loosely): “but what you said is un-Stoic!,” pretty much regardless of what I actually said, or of its logical connection to Stoicism. Anyway, another sign of popularity is the fact that mental health professionals are beginning to take an interest, wishing to empirically assess the effects of practicing Stoicism on people’s psychology.

Since Stoicism itself has from the beginning been a philosophy that included the study of psychology (under the field of “logic”), and moreover has always been explicitly open to revision, this is welcome news. What is not so welcome is when people, predictably, claim that they are studying Stoicism, while in fact they are studying stoicism (for this crucial, and not even that subtle distinction, see this article by Don Robertson).

Which is why a paper published last year in BMJ Open and entitled “Stoic beliefs and health: development and preliminary validation of the Pathak-Wieten Stoicism ideology scale” was a missed opportunity. Authored by Elizabeth Pathak, Sarah Wieten, and Christopher Wheldon, it purports to develop a scale with which to measure, as the title says, Stoic “ideology,” with the purpose of beginning to explore the mental health effects of practicing such ideology. Unfortunately, the paper hopelessly mixes Stoicism and stoicism, with a strong lean toward the latter.

The authors identify four “key domains” of Stoicism: imperviousness to strong emotions, indifference to death, taciturnity, and self-sufficiency. It is on the basis of these domains that they build their scale, which they then test on 390 subjects, most of whom are young students (aged less than 25), mostly white (though somewhat gender balanced), almost all American born.

Setting aside the usual problems with the sampling of subjects used in this sort of study, which there is very little reason to think is representative even of the American population, let alone beyond, let me begin with the four domains just mentioned. I will then move to a brief examination of additional problematic statements made by Pathak and collaborators in the paper.

I. Imperviousness to strong emotions: it is absolutely not the case that this is a Stoic value (although it certainly is a stoic one). Consider, for instance, what Seneca says to his friend Marcia in his letter of consolation to her:

“‘But,’ say you, ‘sorrow for the loss of one’s own children is natural.’ Who denies it? Provided it be reasonable? For we cannot help feeling a pang, and the stoutest-hearted of us are cast down not only at the death of those dearest to us, but even when they leave us on a journey.” (VII)

A bit earlier he writes to her:

“I am not soothing you or making light of your misfortune: if fate can be overcome by tears, let us bring tears to bear upon it: let every day be passed in mourning, every night be spent in sorrow instead of sleep.” (VI)

Does that sound to you like someone who is trying to be impervious to emotions? Or consider just how explicit on the subject Epictetus, notoriously the most stern of the ancient Stoics, really is:

“I must not be without feeling like a statue, but must maintain my natural and acquired relations, as a religious man, as son, brother, father, citizen.” (Discourses III.2)

And here is what modern scholar Margaret Graver, who wrote a whole book on Stoicism and Emotion, says: “If the psychic sensations [i.e., feelings] we experience in emotion are not simply identical with the pathē [i.e., negative emotions], then the norm of apatheia [i.e., lack of negative emotions] does not have to be cashed out as an injunction against every human feeling. One might be impassive in the Stoic sense and still remain subject to other categories of affective experience.”

So, no, the Stoics do not seek to be impervious to emotions. Rather, they work toward improving their judgments about externals, in order to re-align their emotional spectrum, de-emphasizing unhealthy emotions and nurturing and developing healthy ones.

II. Indifference to Death: one can see how people may develop a misconception here, for instance while reading what Seneca writes to Marcia:

“Reflect that the dead suffer no evils, that all those stories which make us dread the nether world are mere fables, that he who dies need fear no darkness, no prison, no blazing streams of fire, no river of Lethe, no judgment seat before which he must appear, and that death is such utter freedom that he need fear no more despots. All that is a phantasy of the poets, who have terrified us without a cause.” (XIX)

This, however, is an explanation of why we should not be afraid of what will happen after we die (because there won’t be any “us” to be concerned by things), it is hardly a council not to care about dying.

True, death — like everything that is not virtue — is categorized within the “indifferents,” either preferred or, in this case, dispreferred. But that word has a very clear technical meaning in Stoic philosophy: it doesn’t mean that one shouldn’t care about dying, but rather that death itself is irrelevant to virtue, in the sense that dying or staying alive, per se, doesn’t make you a better person.

Not convinced? Here is how Epictetus reacts to the news that a friend of his has decided to commit suicide for the hell of it:

“If your decision is justified, look, here we are at your side and ready to help you on your way; but if your decision is unreasonable, you ought to change it. ‘We ought to hold to our decisions.’ — What are you up to, man?” (Discourses II.15.6-7)

Again, does this sound like indifference (in the ordinary sense of the word) to death? I should think not.

III. Taciturnity: stoicism appeals to men, according to the authors, and goes well with the ideal (myth, really) of the solitary man who speaks by his actions. Think Clint Eastwood in The Good, the Bad and the Ugly, or in any of his other movies, for that matter. But Stoicism (the philosophy) advocates nothing of the sort. True, Epictetus famously advises his students to talk little and of important things:

“When you’re called upon to speak, then speak, but never about banalities like gladiators, horses, sports, food and drink — common-place stuff. Above all don’t gossip about people, praising, blaming or comparing them.” (Enchiridion 33.2)

Immediately below, Epictetus adds:

“In your conversation, don’t dwell at excessive length on your own deeds or adventures. Just because you enjoy recounting your exploits doesn’t mean that others derive the same pleasure from hearing about them.” (Enchiridion 33.14)

It’s obvious that this an injunction not to annoy people, and to engage others in meaningful, as opposed to idle, conversation. After all, the Stoics we know of were teachers, senators, generals, and emperors. Hardly the kind of individual who spends his life in a taciturn mood.

IV. Self-sufficiency: here too, stoicism (the attitude) seems to rely on the myth of the solitary hero who depends on no one. But Stoicism (the philosophy) is quintessentially cosmopolitan, and teaches that our primary concern should be to do good on behalf of the human polis. Sure, Marcus is often cited as saying:

“Begin the morning by saying to yourself, I shall meet with the busybody, the ungrateful, arrogant, deceitful, envious, unsocial. All these things happen to them by reason of their ignorance of what is good and evil. … I can neither be injured by any of them, for no one can fix on me what is ugly, nor can I be angry with my kinsman, nor hate him.” (Meditations II.1)

But that’s simply an honest analysis of his expectations about other people qua emperor. He also tells himself in his personal diary:

“Have I been made for this, to lie under the blankets and keep myself warm? But this is more pleasant. Do you exist then to take your pleasure, and not at all for action or exertion?” (Meditations V.1)

And what action and exertion is he referring to, other than the obviously military one (he was encamped on the Danube fighting the Marcomanni tribes when he wrote the above)?

“Do what is necessary, and whatever the reason of a social animal naturally requires, and as it requires.” (Meditations IV.24)

Seneca says something interesting about this matter:

“The wise man is self-sufficient. Nevertheless, he desires friends, neighbours, and associates, no matter how much he is sufficient unto himself.” (IX. On Philosophy and Friendship, 3)

It is clear in context that by “self-sufficient” he means capable of maintaining virtue. And at any rate he is talking about the Sage, which is as rare as the mythical phoenix. He immediately adds that even the Sage desires friends, neighbors, and associates. So, no, there is no basis in Stoicism for the idea of self-sufficiency as understood within the context of stoicism.

This brief analysis should make clear that there is a huge difference between Stoicism and stoicism. Unfortunately, Pathak et al.’s article completely mixes the two, with a far stronger dose of stoicism than Stoicism. The result is a scale that measures something, but definitely not the effects of adopting a Stoic philosophy.

Let us take a look at some quotes from the paper itself, to make sure I am not misinterpreting what the authors are doing. “Stoicism has also been invoked as a defining characteristic of masculinity and as a key explanatory factor for certain health behaviors and outcomes among men” (p. 2 of the online version). This very clearly refers to the stiff upper lip attitude, not the philosophy. Indeed, on the very same page there is mention of the Liverpool Stoicism Scale, which includes “three items that are ideological, for example, ‘one should keep a stiff upper lip.’” Precisely, but no Stoic ever advocated that, so the scale should be renamed the Liverpool stoicism Scale…

Pathak et al. “attempt to articulate an explicitly theory of stoicism [the fact that they are using the lowercase here and elsewhere is not indicative of a distinction being made between the philosophy and common parlance] and its potential impact on health. … stoicism is an ideology … we theorize that people who strongly endorse a personal ideology of stoicism may be more likely to avoid or delay seeking professional medical intervention for serious signs and symptoms of disease” (p. 3)

This can be extremely misleading, if it will lead to adoption of the scale developed in the study for social health research that focuses on stoicism but makes claims about the medical unsoundness of Stoicism.

The results are also difficult to interpret, again because of the complete confounding of stoicism and Stoicism. For instance: “men were more than two times as likely as women to fall into the top quartile of responses” (p. 5), meaning that men agreed more readily with a self-description as “stoic.” “Scores for stoic taciturnity were strongly correlated with scores for both stoic endurance and stoic serenity, but stoic endurance and stoic serenity were not highly correlated with each other. Stoic death indifference … was least correlated with the other three domains” (p. 4). Moreover: “In this study population, respondents were least likely to endorse stoic serenity and most likely to endorse stoic death indifference” (p. 5).

It is hard to know what to make of these findings, since it isn’t clear at all to what mixture of stoicism and Stoicism they refer. Please note, of course, that so far as we know likely none of the participants to the study actually had any training in, or exposure to, Stoic philosophy. Based on that, I’m inclined to say that the relevance of the study to Stoicism is close to zero, while it may tell us a lot about stoicism.

The authors draw some conclusions that seem to me to be rather unsubstantiated, or at least, again, ambiguous as to their referent: “Ironically, a personal ideology of stoicism almost guarantees failure to live up to one’s ideals. … An ideology of stoicism creates an internal resistance to external objective needs, which can lead to negative consequences. … a study of major strain among family caretakers of elderly patients with dementia found those who used stoicism as a coping strategy suffered burnout, while those who sought social support did not” (pp. 6-7).

Right, but that sounds a lot like stoicism, not Stoicism. Now one could perhaps argue that Pathak et al. never actually intended to address Stoic philosophy, only the stiff upper lip modern attitude. But that is clearly not the case from the opening line of the paper: “Stoicism is a school of philosophy which originated in ancient Greece” (p. 1).

Which makes some of their conclusions particularly troublesome, especially for people who are trying to practice the philosophy: “We hypothesise that illness behaviors may become ‘noncompliant’ or ‘irrational’ or ‘self-harming’ when specific courses of action would create an internal conflict with patients’ ideas of who they are. … This internal conflict will lead to delays in or avoidance of help seeking, with potentially life-threatening consequences. For example, empirical studies of male suicide in rural Australia have identified hegemonic masculine norms of stoicism as an important causal factor in the context of severe economic stress” (p. 8).

The situation of rural men in Australia subject to economic stress and committing suicide at high rates is horrible, but it does not seem to have anything to do with Seneca, Epictetus, and Marcus Aurelius, names that are very likely entirely unknown to the people in question. It is therefore highly misleading, dangerous, and — I’m sorry to say — irresponsible to so casually mix stoicism and Stoicism.

Of course, as Don Robertson points out in his article on the matter, the same problem applies to other philosophies. I can easily see a study of “epicureanism” showing that if people indulge frequently in large meals, a lot of drinking, and unprotected sex with multiple patterns, they will incur health risks. But to blame Epicurus — who argued for restrain in or abstention from all the just mentioned activities — would be bizarre.

So I urge Elizabeth Pathak, Sarah Wieten, and Christopher Wheldon to scrap the whole exercise, ideally retracting their paper, and writing up their findings again while making crystal clear what they mean by “stoicism.” Better yet, since there is a philosophy that has carried that name for the past 23 centuries, avoid to use the term altogether and write a paper on how to measure the potentially negative health consequences of trying to live like Clint Eastwood in a Western movie. The underlying problem — that an image of extreme self-reliance is bad for one’s health — is likely real and deserves attention. But the relevant research ought to be carried out properly.

13 thoughts on “Stoicism, stoicism, and mental health

  1. Tim Dubber

    An excellent article on the constant issue of image management – something a little odd to be talking about in this forum if you consider the Stoic position on the opinions of others as externals and your reputation as something beyond your control. However, Socrates himself is a perfect example of what happens when others are able to dominate the narrative and cast you in whatever light they want.

    As an Australian, I was quite interested in the example you gave of rural Australian men (I apologise for the parochialism). I agree with your assessment of such a statement as a conflation of ‘big S’ Stoicism with what has become increasingly known in modern parlance as ‘Toxic Masculinity’.

    It would be interesting for those mental health professionals who specifically assist in dealing with people suffering from PTSD to provide some insight into the way in which focusing on the act of trauma as opposed to attempting to transcend it impacts on an individual’s mental recovery.
    Thank you for a delightful read.

    Tim

    Liked by 1 person

  2. Massimo Post author

    Tim,

    Thanks for your comments from down under. One thing I’d like to gently push back: yes, it is true that other people’s opinions ultimately are not up to us. But there is nothing in Stoicism that says one has to sit back and shut up, letting untrue or unjust things being said or happening. Hence this article…

    Liked by 5 people

  3. Tim Dubber

    Apologies, I should have used my irony punctuation ⸮

    I definitely agree with your argument, and I think that the case of the Epicureans and Early Christians (along with the cult of Mithra once the positions of power had been reversed) are great classical examples of this issue. When these small sects were unable to control the narrative around their own doctrines and dogma, they essentially had their image defined in the popular eye by their enemies.

    Not to suggest that anyone criticising Stoicism is an enemy – merely that the prevalent use of the term is often being equated with what is now seen as part of the ‘bad’ masculinity that social justice and men’s mental health advocates are attempting to disassemble in their quest for a better society.

    Cheers,

    Tim

    Liked by 2 people

  4. Chris Visser

    ‘Toxic Masculinity’ -nice one. Well Massimo, welcome to the world of charlatans and snake oil-sellers. Don’t spend too much time on these people, they have reasons of their own and do the best to their abilities.
    Good crisp article.
    regards Chris

    Liked by 1 person

  5. virtue42015

    As one born in Liverpool I was intrigued to learn of a “Liverpool Stoicism Scale”.

    A few minutes online research tracked it down to a 1995 paper by Professors Wagstaff and Rowledge of Liverpool University, which posited: “A scale was developed to test the hypotheses that stoicism would be more prevalent in British men (n = 30) than in British women (n = 32) and that stoicism would be related to negative attitudes toward the poor. It was also hypothesized that stoics would exhibit a weaker emotional reaction to stories that had emotive content. All three hypotheses were supported. There was evidence that the Stoicism Scale had internal consistency and some external validity.”

    As an aspiring Stoic I have difficulty reconciling the implied interpretation of lower case ‘stoicism’ with what I believe the philosophy of “Stoicism” to be about.

    Like

  6. Priamus (@en_priamus)

    The authors cite the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy in order to establish that “core elements in the classical definition of stoicism were an idealisation of imperviousness to strong emotions, and an indifference to death”. However, that encyclopedia’s article on Stoicism (1) apparently says nothing of the sort.

    They also cite three articles as “previous research on stoicism and health”: (2) Human health and stoic moral norms, (3) A New Stoic: The Wise Patient and (4) Troubling stoicism: Sociocultural influences and applications to health and illness behaviour. The first article is pretty philosophical and talks about Stoicism. The other two articles discuss what it means to be a stoic/Stoic, with quotes such as:

    From the second article: “For the Stoic, happiness consists in living in accord with nature. Stoics are sometimes portrayed as apathetic fatalists, silently accepting whatever misfortune might come their way, but this is a misunderstanding.”
    From the third article: “As time has passed, the meaning of what it is to be stoical has changed. The label is applied uncritically to those who do not complain, but can we really call this stoicism?”

    I think their article is pretty good in general — they just didn’t care too much about distinguishing the ancient philosophy from the modern meaning, like the articles they cite. I don’t think that warrants a retraction. People who know a little about Stoicism would immediately understand what’s going on. Beginners who are trying to learn the philosophy by looking up scientific articles would be savvy enough to not trust a single article anyway.

    (1) https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/stoicism/

    (2) http://digitalcommons.hollins.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1007&context=philfac

    (3) http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/pdf/10.1080/03605310490503542

    (4) http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/pdf/10.1177/1363459312451179

    Liked by 1 person

  7. Massimo Post author

    Virtue,

    “A scale was developed to test the hypotheses that stoicism would be more prevalent in British men (n = 30) than in British women (n = 32) and that stoicism would be related to negative attitudes toward the poor. It was also hypothesized that stoics would exhibit a weaker emotional reaction to stories that had emotive content. All three hypotheses were supported.”

    As you say, this makes clear that the scale as nothing to do with the philosophy.

    Priamus,

    “I think their article is pretty good in general — they just didn’t care too much about distinguishing the ancient philosophy from the modern meaning, like the articles they cite. I don’t think that warrants a retraction”

    I disagree. They clearly misconstrue the philosophy and make a mess of the confusion between it and the attitude. Just on those grounds the article should have been rejected by the editor.

    Moreover, it may tell honest practitioners of Stoicism that they’ll end up more likely to die early or commit suicide. That’s grossly irresponsible.

    Liked by 5 people

  8. Girish Mangtani

    “Tim,

    Thanks for your comments from down under. One thing I’d like to gently push back: yes, it is true that other people’s opinions ultimately are not up to us. But there is nothing in Stoicism that says one has to sit back and shut up, letting untrue or unjust things being said or happening. Hence this article…”

    Massimo,

    I’m a novice and recently started reading about Stoicism. I’ve been bullied all my life and have been searching for ways to deal with that. Recently, I started getting physically angry at the slightest provocation thinking that that would scare bullies off. However, I still struggle with that, to the point that it’s affecting me emotionally and mentally. I’ve read Bill Irvine’s book; Bill’s insult pacifism advice feels a lot like defeatism which still leaves me emotionally upset. What advice would you give me as to how to deal with bullies and/or people saying unjust things? Thank you much.

    GM

    Like

  9. Plutarch

    I think Massimo is entirely right.

    Caricaturing and confusing Stoicism (the proper noun/philosophy) as being stoic (adjective/understood as something bad) is irresponsible in a peer reviewed journal.

    Even if mistakenly mixing up the two is completely understandable since most people are unaware of the difference between Stoicism and stoicism, a peer reviewed journal on the subject of mental health is, and should be, held to a higher standard of rigor.

    Given that Stoicism is about aiding others and oneself, among other many other wonderful things, I think it is entirely consistent that Massimo, as a Stoic, speak up and explain when Stoicism is being confused for mere stoicism. It would be stoic -rather than Stoic- for Massimo to say nothing and grit his teeth when the name of Stoicism was being tarnished.

    Liked by 1 person

  10. Massimo Post author

    Girish,

    Well, this thread isn’t really the best place to give advice based on Stoic principles, I have a separate column for that (http://tinyurl.com/lcxdnz8). That said, I disagree that insult pacifism is a form of defeatism. You are showing yourself superior to the bully by not lowering yourself to his level. The fact that he can’t possibly understand that is irrelevant.

    However, don’t forget that there is nothing in Stoicism that forbids one to take action when an injustice is being done. On the contrary, a Stoic ought to take action. So if there is anything you can do, like file a complaint with your employer (if it is a work-related situation) or even the police (if the behavior warrants it), you should.

    Like

  11. walreis

    I can’t agree more with the overall objective of this essay, which is straightforwardly applicable to the majority of findings in philosophy and science, once ‘common sense’ versions of them start to appear from their divulgation. But this is a matter that boils down to the subject ‘education’ and how on average it is dealt with lightly worldwide: the abilty to examine theories with the required self-detachement, I mean, the required critical vision seems not to be among the chief targets in schools in general, and isn’t certainly considered in the common sense itself – we all know about it.

    However this doesn’t preclude, in the case of the Stoicism, that we must acknowledge its radical ‘mutation’ from the early times of Zeno up to reaching the Roman patricians, and even up to mixing itself – to a considerable extent – with the young Christian doctrine. I have some doubts about how or whether Zeno and his first followers would have recognized their Stoicism after it have fallen in the hands of people at the top of the ‘social pyramid’ – this statement may also be applied to Epictetus, in spite of his conscpicuous presence in the work of M. Aurelius (who had to make wars…). Massimo’s essay on the core of Stoicism is very illuminating, but I feel it isn’t still enough in order to put all those transformations in their due places.

    And, finally, Massimo,

    As the comments to the your last post have been closed, I put here what you asked me there.

    I believe that in general we agree very closely on that confusing subject involving reason, feelings, sensations and their ‘naturalness’. And if perchance we’ve been differing from one another, it was in the ways we exposed it, not to say that beyond the lack of concision, my way of writing things down isn’t indeed focused on making the arguments easier. Besides this we may have disagreed about what origins what, which is not such a big issue, considering how ordinarily it appears in every field of knowledge.

    Like

  12. Massimo Post author

    Walreis,

    Interesting comment. However, I’m in the midst of reading Margaret Graver’s Stoicism and Emotion (doing a commentary on this blog, as you probably know), and she states pretty clearly that both Seneca and Epictetus did not actually depart that much from Zeno and Chrysippus. They provided their own interpretations, twists, and occasional innovation. But nothing radical, as far as she could tell.

    Like

  13. walreis

    Massimo,

    Your posts had already convinced me that Graver’s book worth a serious reading.

    I might also say that I sensed Seneca was close to Epictetus, but at the time I read some of his letters I was still under the deep impression the Discourses and the Enchiridion left on me. I plan to remedy this a.s.a.p.

    Liked by 1 person

Comments are closed.